Skip to main content

Genotype-driven recruitment: a strategy whose time has come?

Abstract

Background

Genotype-Driven Recruitment (GDR) is a research design that recruits research participants based on genotype rather than based on the presence or absence of a particular condition or clinical outcome. Analyses of the ethical issues of GDR studies, and the recommendations derived from these analyses, are based on GDR research designs that make use of genetic information already collected in previous studies. However, as genotyping becomes more affordable, it is expected that genotypic information will become a common part of the information stored in biobanks and held in health care records. Furthermore, individuals will increasingly gain knowledge of their own genotypes through Direct-to-Consumer services. One can therefore foresee that individuals will be invited to participate not only in follow-up GDR studies but also in original GDR studies because genetic information about them is available. These individuals may or may have not participated in research before and may or may not be aware that their genetic information is available for research.

Discussion

From a conceptual point of view, we investigate whether the current ethics-related recommendations for the conduct of GDR suffice for a broader array of circumstances under which genetic information can be available. Our analysis reveals that the existing recommendations do not suffice for a broader use of GDR.

Summary

Our findings refocus attention on ethical issues which are neither new nor specific to GDR but which place greater demand on coordinated solutions. These challenges and approaches for addressing them are discussed.

Peer Review reports

Background

Biobanks and genomic studies are accumulating large numbers of samples and generating databases that create novel research opportunities within the biomedical and behavioural sciences. An increasingly important design used in genetic research is called Genotype-Driven Recruitment (GDR) [1, 2]. In GDR, research participants are not recruited based on the presence or absence of a particular condition (e.g. diabetes or high blood pressure) but are rather recruited based on their genotype characteristics such as the presence of a particular gene variant (e.g. a specific polymorphism or a gene deletion) [1, 2]. GDR is a particularly useful design for studying the role of specific genotypes on health-related outcomes including differences in disease susceptibility, differential responses to interventions and treatments or normal variation in developmental outcomes. GDR studies have great potential to increase the utility of genomic data generated in diverse settings and thereby can accelerate the translational process towards benefiting human health [13].

The ethical implications of GDR have been recently discussed in the literature and recommendations have been made to address these issues [118]. However, these recommendations were derived from analyses of GDR designs that recruit via re-contact of individuals for whom genetic data already exists because they have participated in a study that collected and analyzed DNA. In this paper, we examine from a conceptual point of view, whether the ethics-related recommendations which have been proposed under circumstances of re-contact for GDR research sufficiently cover the ethical concerns that can arise as opportunities to use GDR increase with the growing availability of genotypic data. In particular, we focus on the ethical and societal implications of recruiting individuals in original GDR studies because genetic information about them is known or available through, for example, health care medical records or health records from Direct-to-Consumer (DTC) genetic testing services. These individuals may or may have not participated in research before and may or may not be aware that their genetic information is available for research.

Potential future uses of GDR

Current studies employing GDR are primarily follow-up studies making secondary use of genetic information collected in previous studies [13, 7, 9, 14, 17]. As genotyping becomes more affordable, the use of GDR studies will most likely expand for two main reasons. First, individuals may be recruited into GDR studies because their genetic information is made available through the health care system. Several projects are currently planning to sequence entire populations or large groups of individuals and store their genetic information in healthcare databases. These projects are designed with the objective to 1) offer better disease diagnosis, therapy and clinical outcome for patients through integrated analysis of clinical, biological, environmental and genetic data [19] and 2) produce datasets that may be made available to national and international researchers through the approval of data access applications. For example, the FarGen project [20] plans to sequence the whole population of the Faroe Islands (approximately 50,000 individuals) within the coming years. The population of the Faroe Islands is particularly interesting for researchers because it is a small homogenous population with a high incidence of rare hereditary diseases [21]. It is therefore expected that the genetic information produced through the FarGen project will be an attractive resource to conduct GDR studies. Another example is the British National Health Service’s (NHS) plan to build a massive database in which every British citizen’s DNA records will be stored and made accessible to researchers from public and private institutions [22, 23]. Both the Faroese and the British project plan that the genetic data produced will be stored in patient records and linkable to other health registries [20, 23]. These types of collections are invaluable for conducting GDR studies that will play an important role in advancing the goals of precision medicine [19]. Although it is still unclear which requirements and limitations will apply for access to the data produced through these projects (e.g. access to coded or encrypted datasets), one can foresee that GDR will be in high demand and procedures to conduct GDR will need to be established.

A second reason why the potential to recruit individuals through GDR may increase is because an individual’s genetic information may be made available through DTC genetic testing companies. The last years have seen the emergence of a myriad of private companies which offer genetic screening services to consumers at an affordable price [24]. The privacy policies of these companies often do not guarantee that genetic data will not be shared with third parties and sometimes even state that genetic data may be shared for research purposes or sold in the event of company dissolution, merger or acquisition [24, 25]. For instance, the DTC genetic testing company 23andMe is now seeking collaborations with academic researchers to maximise the scientific yield from their database [26]. The company highlights that research on rare genotype-phenotype combinations is one of the proposed areas of collaboration [26]. It is also foreseen that future business plans of DTC companies will give greater priority to selling DTC customer data to commercial entities to increase their return on investment [27, 28]. Under such conditions, it is likely that the genetic data of the customers of DTC companies could be made accessible to researchers who want to conduct GDR studies.

If, as we believe, opportunities for GDR-based studies expand with the growing generation of genotypic data it is critical to investigate how this impacts the ethical landscape of GDR.

Methods

A literature search was conducted using Pubmed and Google Scholar to identify studies that describe a) ethical issues in GDR-based research and, b) current recommendations to address those issues. Only articles which specifically discussed or mentioned the ethical aspects of GDR were selected from the search results [118]. An overview of the ethical issues identified and the recommendations made to address each of these issues was then compiled.

Next, a conceptual analysis was conducted that examined whether each of the ethical issues identified was sufficiently handled under the current set of recommendations for the cases where individuals were not re-contacted for a follow-up GDR study but contacted to participate in an original GDR study because their genetic information is available in public or private health care records. The information generated from this analysis is described herein and serves as the basis upon which we conclude whether the current recommendations suffice under the broader utilization of GDR.

Results

Results of our literature review reveal that the main ethical issues associated with GDR are related to the re-contact of research participants and the disclosure to them of their genetic information during the recruitment phase [14, 6, 7, 9, 14, 17]. Table 1 provides an overview of our analysis results including the ethical concerns identified, recommendations forwarded to address these, whether the current recommendations adequately address the ethical concerns raised under a broader utilization of GDR and the reasoning behind these determinations.

Table 1 Overview of ethical concerns in GDR and assessment whether current recommendations suffice for a broader use of GDR

Ethical concerns in GDR

GDR based on the secondary use of previously collected genotype data requires that the research participants be re-contacted for the purpose of recruitment into the study. Because genotypic information is the basis for the recruitment, GDR may implicitly result in researchers providing participants with some information about their genotype as well as other information related to their medical or health status [1]. However, providing such information during recruitment might violate the individual’s privacy and right not to know about their own genetic information [14]. It may also create anxiety and distress for the individual who might think that something is wrong about her health since she has been re-contacted [1, 2]. By contrast, not providing such information at recruitment may be perceived by the individual as a form of deception because she would not know why she has been enrolled in the study [1].

Issues surrounding the divulgence of genetic results are at the crux of the ethical considerations in GDR. Today, the return of research results from genetic studies to research participants is a highly debated topic among scientists, ethicists and policy makers [2931]. Current guidelines typically sanction the return of genetic results if they are actionable or clinically useful for the research participants [18, 3234]. However, to harness the full scientific potential of GDR designs, it is quite likely that the genetic selection criteria for recruiting participants will not meet the requirements of being actionable or clinically useful. Not providing genetic results may mask the reasons why participants have been enrolled in the study [1, 7], but disclosing genetic results requires certain types of guidance for the participant. This process is compounded when results are experimental, partly unreliable or uncertified and may have serious consequences for the research participants who may make further health-related decisions based on shallow scientific ground [1, 3, 5]. However, even when the results are verified in clinical labs, the finding of a rare variant could also have dramatic consequences for the individuals concerned because they may affect their health and make them the carriers of bad news for their family members [1, 4, 9].

Re-contact for recruitment into a GDR study may also put the individuals re-contacted and their relatives in a difficult situation, especially if the study design (e.g. case only study) allows outsiders to determine which genetic variant is under study [1, 2]. Finally, there is a risk that individuals with rare genetic variants may begin to feel overwhelmed if they receive numerous invitations to join GDR studies [1, 2]. This could, in the long term, discourage individuals from participating in research.

Published recommendations

A number of recommendations have been made to address the issues surrounding the return of genetic results described above and primarily focus on optimising the informed consent process and developing mechanisms for feedback of results to research participants. This is illustrated by recommendations to 1) include information about potential re-contact and future disclosure in the original consent [2, 6, 7, 12]; 2) offer participants the opportunity to choose whether or not they want to be re-contacted for future participation in GDR studies [24, 6, 7]; and 3) ensure that re-contact occurs by a known and trusted health professional [3, 4, 7].

In addition, it is recommended that independent governance bodies determine, in close co-operation with the Institutional Review Boards (IRB) of the original studies, which individuals to re-contact and how to re-contact them [2, 6, 7, 10]. Other recommendations include 1) choosing a study design which prevents the involuntary disclosure of information about the genetic profile of the research participants to the outside world, e.g. by adding randomly selected sub-groups in case-only studies [1]; 2) using less stringent parameters for the return of results to research participants than currently recommended in other genetic research [1, 3, 6, 7, 9, 15, 17] and 3) return of results according to specific criteria agreed upon in co-operation with the research participants [8, 15].

Finally, a general recommendation is that researchers who plan to conduct GDR studies should take into consideration the context of the research (e.g. was the original study conducted by different researchers than the follow-up GDR study?) and the relationship between the researchers and the individuals they plan to invite [5, 7, 9].

Do the recommendations suffice under a broader use of GDR?

Results from our conceptual analysis reveal that out of 15 recommendations proposed in the current literature only one may suffice in the context of a broader use of GDR. The recommendation to add randomly selected sub-groups in case-only studies to avoid risks of stigmatisation when individuals are invited to GDR studies may also be applicable when GDR studies are original studies and not follow-up studies. For each of the remaining fourteen recommendations, we found one or several reasons why the current recommendations would not suffice in a context of broader use of GDR designs. These reasons are reported in Table 1 and can be summarised as follows.

The individuals invited to enroll in an original GDR study may not be prepared to receive such an invitation

Current recommendations presuppose that, at some point in time, an informed consent process has taken place between researchers and participants; a process during which information about potential future enrolment in GDR studies has been provided and the opportunity for participants to indicate whether they want to be involved in future GDR has been given. Recommendations also suggest that re-contact should be undertaken by a known professional such as the principal investigator of the study to which the participant was originally recruited. However, this type of individual informed consent process may not systematically take place in conjunction with the generation of genotypic information. An example would be genotyping conducted through standard health care where informed consent may not have been required. Individuals who are not aware that genetic information exists about them will probably be totally unprepared if contacted for participation in a GDR study [14]. Even individuals who have previous knowledge about their genotype from DTC genetic testing services may not be aware that their genetic information potentially could have been sold to or shared with other private companies or researchers [25]. Thus, unexpected contact may come as a surprise and provoke anger if the individuals contacted do not want to know about own genetic information and do not want their relatives to know [1, 3, 4, 9].

The individuals invited to enroll in an original GDR study may not be prepared to receive genetic research results

When individuals who have participated in previous research are re-contacted for participation in a GDR study, they already have some knowledge about what a research study entails and what participating in research means. They have taken the initiative to participate in research and may have received some basic information related to the genetic research aims by the investigators of the original study. Things may be different for individuals who are not re-contacted but contacted for the first time; individuals who have never participated in research before and may not know anything about genetic research. There is currently no empirical evidence on the effects of receiving genetic results without having been prepared to it. One could argue that the disclosure of genetic research results to research participants normally does not trigger such distress as shown in recent studies [35, 36]. However, the recipients of genetic results who participated in those studies already had a relationship with the researchers or were aware of the presence of a genetic variant in their family through a relative’s participation in research or illness. If individuals are recruited into original GDR studies through e.g. their health care system or directly by a private company, such a relationship and awareness may not exist.

Current recommendations also encourage applying a lower threshold than usual for feedback of results from GDR [1, 3, 6, 7, 9, 15, 17]. A sound feedback process that respects the perspectives and wishes of participants typically requires taking into consideration the context of the research and the relationship between the researcher and the research participant [8, 15]. However, if as we postulate, GDR designs were used more broadly, it would not always be possible for researchers to make such an assessment because they may not know anything about the individual’s previous involvement in research.

The establishment of independent governance bodies to coordinate all GDR research projects may be too challenging

The current recommendations encourage the establishment of independent governance bodies, e.g. centralised ethics or data access committees, by the projects generating genetic information to manage all data access requests, protect the privacy and confidentiality of datasets and determine which individuals can be contacted and by whom. The objective of establishing these committees is to avoid harassing individuals by inviting them to multiple studies as could be the case, for example, for individuals carrying a rare genetic variant, and ensure that ethical standards are respected [2, 7, 10]. Creation of such committees raises several sets of questions. First, questions related to the legal authority of these committees may emerge. For instance, under which legal framework, national or international, would these committees be established and operate? Could these committees have authority both over publicly financed research projects and private companies? As an example, DTC genetic testing companies currently do not operate under the same legal framework as publicly funded research projects [37] and, although attempts to regulate their activities have been made, they still benefit from a rather loose legal framework [38]. Unless international regulation requires that DTC genetic testing companies follow the same rules (and report to the same centralised committees) as publicly funded research projects, it is quite unlikely that they will do so.

Second, questions related to the scientific authority of these committees may emerge. How could these committees for instance make decisions regarding data access requests from numerous public and private actors? To do so would probably require that the committees have extensive knowledge about all research projects previously undergone, which individuals have participated in which research projects and which have not, which have consented to re-contact and which have not, which have already been invited in previous GDR studies, and which have not etc. Such a high level of co-ordination could maybe be possible between publicly-funded institutions within a specific research collaboration or geographic area [10] but seem quite unrealistic to expect when both publicly funded research projects and a myriad of private companies are involved.

Discussion

We investigated whether current recommendations to address ethical issues in GDR suffice when GDR studies are original studies recruiting individuals from whom genetic information is available through, for example, health care medical records or health records from DTC genetic testing services. These individuals may or may not have participated in a research study and may or may not be aware that their genetic information is available for research. The current recommendations are useful when planning studies that will produce genotypic information of interest for future GDR. However, they were not developed to address potential issues that may arise if original GDR studies become more common due to the availability of individual genotypic information generated from a wider and more diverse array of sources.

From a conceptual point of view, we foresee that a broader use of GDR will call attention to a number of issues that are neither new nor specific to GDR per se but for which coordinated solutions will be strongly needed. Examples include:

  1. 1)

    How to deal with the dissemination of genetic information of uncertain value and utility towards groups of individuals that are unaware that such information exists about them and are insufficiently educated to understand the meaning of it;

  2. 2)

    How to widely disseminate information about genetic variants to individuals through the conduct of GDR studies without provoking the unnecessary medicalization of otherwise healthy individuals [39];

  3. 3)

    How to respectfully disseminate information about genetic variation to individuals about their own genotypes but which has implications at the familial level [4, 17];

  4. 4)

    How to avoid provoking more genetic determinism and increasing potential risks of stigmatisation and discrimination of individuals when genotypes become a common selection criteria for invitation in research studies [40]; and,

  5. 5)

    How to avoid invitation-fatigue of individuals whose genotypes are highly sought after for biomedical research.

Summary

There are growing opportunities for important research using GDR designs and recent studies show that research participants have a rather positive attitude towards GDR designs and understand their scientific value [3, 9, 15, 17]. The recommendations that have been published to address ethical concerns in GDR are useful but should be complemented by other strategies to address new challenges for GDR designs that originate outside of a study-specific research setting. These strategies cannot be addressed by the researchers conducting GDR studies alone but need to be addressed at a broader level by health authorities, the scientific community from both public and private sectors, and policy makers. Such strategies may be bolstered by the development of tools to promote education, dissemination and public engagement. Examples include tools to: 1) widely inform the public about genetic research activities and the production of genetic information through health care systems and private companies; 2) provide all groups in society with basic education in genetics; 3) widely inform about the right to opt-out from research and the right not to know about one’s own genetic information; 4) protect and secure these rights in a co-ordinated manner across privately and publicly funded research projects, and 5) facilitate an increased involvement of the public in the design of research projects.

Abbreviations

GDR:

Genotype-Driven Recruitment

IRB:

Institutional Review Board.

References

  1. Beskow LM, Linney KN, Radtke RA, Heinzen EL, Goldstein DB: Ethical challenges in genotype-driven research recruitment. Genome Res. 2010, 20: 705-709. 10.1101/gr.104455.109.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  2. McGuire SE, McGuire AL: Don’t throw the baby out with the bathwater: enabling a bottom-up approach in genome-wide association studies. Genome Res. 2008, 18: 1683-1685. 10.1101/gr.083584.108.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  3. Beskow LM, Namey EE, Cadigan RJ, Brazg T, Crouch J, Henderson GE, Michie M, Nelson DK, Tabor HK, Wilfond BS: Research participants’ perspectives on genotype-driven research recruitment. J Empir Res Hum Res Ethics. 2011, 6: 3-20.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  4. Beskow LM, Botkin JR, Daly M, Juengst ET, Lehmann LS, Merz JF, Pentz R, Press NA, Ross LF, Sugarman J: Ethical issues in identifying and recruiting participants for familial genetic research. Am J Med Genet A. 2004, 130A: 424-431. 10.1002/ajmg.a.30234.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  5. Beskow LM, Burke W: Offering individual genetic research results: context matters. Sci Transl Med. 2010, 2: 38cm20-10.1126/scitranslmed.3000952.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  6. Beskow LM, Namey EE, Miller PR, Nelson DK, Cooper A: IRB chairs’ perspectives on genotype-driven research recruitment. IRB. 2012, 34: 1-10.

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  7. Beskow LM, Fullerton SM, Namey EE, Nelson DK, Davis AM, Wilfond BS: Recommendations for ethical approaches to genotype-driven research recruitment. Hum Genet. 2012, 131: 1423-1431. 10.1007/s00439-012-1177-z.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  8. Budin-Ljøsne I: A review of ethical frameworks for the disclosure of individual research results in population-based genetic and genomic research. Research Ethics. 2012, 8: 25-42. 10.1177/1747016111435576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Cadigan RJ, Michie M, Henderson G, Davis AM, Beskow LM: The meaning of genetic research results: reflections from individuals with and without a known genetic disorder. J Empir Res Hum Res Ethics. 2011, 6: 30-40. 10.1525/jer.2011.6.4.30.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  10. Caulfield T, McGuire AL, Cho M, Buchanan JA, Burgess MM, Danilczyk U, Diaz CM, Fryer-Edwards K, Green SK, Hodosh MA: Research ethics recommendations for whole-genome research: consensus statement. PLoS Biol. 2008, 6: e73-10.1371/journal.pbio.0060073.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  11. Henderson GE, Juengst ET, King NM, Kuczynski K, Michie M: What research ethics should learn from genomics and society research: lessons from the ELSI Congress of 2011. J Law Med Ethics. 2012, 40: 1008-1024.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  12. McGuire AL, Beskow LM: Informed consent in genomics and genetic research. Annu Rev Genomics Hum Genet. 2010, 11: 361-381. 10.1146/annurev-genom-082509-141711.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  13. McGuire AL, Lupski JR: Personal genome research : what should the participant be told?. Trends Genet. 2010, 26: 199-201. 10.1016/j.tig.2009.12.007.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  14. Michie M, Cadigan RJ, Henderson G, Beskow LM: Am I a control? Genotype-driven research recruitment and self-understandings of study participants. Genet Med. 2012, 14: 983-989. 10.1038/gim.2012.88.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  15. Namey EE, Beskow LM: Epilepsy patient-participants and genetic research results as “answers”. J Empir Res Hum Res Ethics. 2011, 6: 21-29.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  16. Oliver JM, McGuire AL: Exploring the ELSI universe: critical issues in the evolution of human genomic research. Genome Med. 2011, 3: 38-10.1186/gm254.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  17. Tabor HK, Brazg T, Crouch J, Namey EE, Fullerton SM, Beskow LM, Wilfond BS: Parent perspectives on pediatric genetic research and implications for genotype-driven research recruitment. J Empir Res Hum Res Ethics. 2011, 6: 41-52. 10.1525/jer.2011.6.4.41.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  18. Wolf SM, Crock BN, Van NB, Lawrenz F, Kahn JP, Beskow LM, Cho MK, Christman MF, Green RC, Hall R: Managing incidental findings and research results in genomic research involving biobanks and archived data sets. Genet Med. 2012, 14: 361-384. 10.1038/gim.2012.23.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  19. National Research Council: Toward Precision Medicine: Building a Knowledge Network for Biomedical Research and a New Taxonomy of Disease. 2011, Washington, DC: The National Academies Press

    Google Scholar 

  20. FarGen project. [http://cphx.org/2012/08/bogi-eliasen-sequencing-the-entire-nation-of-the-faroe-islands/]

  21. Jakobsen RK: Sequencing the genome of an entire population. [http://sciencenordic.com/sequencing-genome-entire-population]

  22. Doward J: Plans for NHS database of patients’ DNA angers privacy campaigners. [http://www.guardian.co.uk/politics/2012/dec/09/dna-database-nhs-gene-genomics]

  23. Human Genomics Strategy Group: Building on our inheritance - Genomic technology in health care. [https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/134568/dh_132382.pdf.pdf]

  24. Health Law Institute University of Alberta: Analysis of Privacy Policies and Practices of Direct-to-Consumer Genetic Testing Companies: Private Sector Databanks and Privacy Protection Norms. [http://www.heals.ualberta.ca/People/ExternalResearchFellows/NolaMRies/~/media/heals/ResearchDocuments/OPCC_Report_March_28_2010.pdf]

  25. Vorhaus D, Moore L: What happens if a DTC genomics company goes belly up?. [http://www.genomicslawreport.com/index.php/2009/09/18/what-happens-if-a-dtc-genomics-company-goes-belly-up/]

  26. 23anMe Research Portal Call for Academic Collaborators: [https://www.23andme.com/researchportal/]

  27. Obasogie OK: Googling Your Genes?. [http://www.biopoliticaltimes.org/article.php?id=3536]

  28. Shanks P: New Business Plans for the Direct-to-Consumer Gene Testing Industry?. [http://www.biopoliticaltimes.org/article.php?id=6552]

  29. Dressler LG, Juengst ET: Thresholds and boundaries in the disclosure of individual genetic research results. Am J Bioeth. 2006, 6: 18-20.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  30. Fernandez CV, Weijer C: Obligations in offering to disclose genetic research results. Am J Bioeth. 2006, 6: 44-46.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  31. Shalowitz DI, Miller FG: Disclosing individual results of clinical research: implications of respect for participants. JAMA. 2005, 294: 737-740. 10.1001/jama.294.6.737.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  32. Fabsitz RR, McGuire A, Sharp RR, Puggal M, Beskow LM, Biesecker LG, Bookman E, Burke W, Burchard EG, Church G: Ethical and practical guidelines for reporting genetic research results to study participants: updated guidelines from a national heart, lung, and blood institute working group. Circ Cardiovasc Genet. 2010, 3: 574-580. 10.1161/CIRCGENETICS.110.958827.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  33. Knoppers BM, Laberge C: Return of “accurate” and “actionable” results: yes!. Am J Bioeth. 2009, 9: 107-109. 10.1080/15265160902918788.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  34. Knoppers BM, Deschenes M, Zawati MH, Tasse AM: Population studies: return of research results and incidental findings Policy Statement. Eur J Hum Genet. 2013, 21: 245-247. 10.1038/ejhg.2012.152.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  35. Green RC, Roberts JS, Cupples LA, Relkin NR, Whitehouse PJ, Brown T, Eckert SL, Butson M, Sadovnick AD, Quaid KA: Disclosure of APOE genotype for risk of Alzheimer’s disease. N Engl J Med. 2009, 361: 245-254. 10.1056/NEJMoa0809578.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  36. Christensen KD, Roberts JS, Shalowitz DI, Everett JN, Kim SY, Raskin L, Gruber SB: Disclosing individual CDKN2A research results to melanoma survivors: interest, impact, and demands on researchers. Cancer Epidemiol Biomarkers Prev. 2011, 20: 522-529. 10.1158/1055-9965.EPI-10-1045.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  37. Borry P, van Hellemondt RE, Sprumont D, Jales CF, Rial-Sebbag E, Spranger TM, Curren L, Kaye J, Nys H, Howard H: Legislation on direct-to-consumer genetic testing in seven European countries. Eur J Hum Genet. 2012, 20: 715-721. 10.1038/ejhg.2011.278.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  38. Vorhaus D: What five FDA letters mean for the future of DTC genetic testing?. [http://www.genomicslawreport.com/index.php/2010/06/11/what-five-fda-letters-mean-for-the-future-of-dtc-genetic-testing/]

  39. Arnason V, Hjorleifsson S: Geneticization and bioethics: advancing debate and research. Med Health Care Philos. 2007, 10: 417-431. 10.1007/s11019-007-9088-9.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  40. Evans JP, Burke W: Genetic exceptionalism. Too much of a good thing?. Genet Med. 2008, 10: 500-501. 10.1097/GIM.0b013e31817f280a.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Pre-publication history

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work was supported through funds from the European Union’s Seventh Framework Programmes ENGAGE Consortium, grant agreement HEALTH-F4-2007-201413; BioSHaRE-EU, grant agreement HEALTH-F4-2010-261433; and Biobank Norway, funded by the Norwegian Research Council (NFR 197443/F50).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Isabelle Budin-Ljøsne.

Additional information

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Authors’ contributions

AMT, JRH, IBL and BMK conceived of the study. IBL and KJS drafted and critically revised the manuscript. AMT, JRH and BMK participated in its design, and critically revised the manuscript. All authors read and approved the final manuscript.

Rights and permissions

This article is published under license to BioMed Central Ltd. This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/2.0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Budin-Ljøsne, I., Soye, K.J., Tassé, A.M. et al. Genotype-driven recruitment: a strategy whose time has come?. BMC Med Genomics 6, 19 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1186/1755-8794-6-19

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/1755-8794-6-19

Keywords